Ralph Waldo Emerson’s career was
characterized both by reformation and reconciliation. It is easy to read too much into the often
fiery rhetoric of Emerson’s speeches and come to see him primarily as an
iconoclast, but this would be a great oversight. Emerson was, however, a very progressive
thinker and he seemed to have a constitutional affinity for a sort of skeptical
optimism. Never content to merely accept
traditions at face value, Emerson knew at an early age that he had a higher
calling: “I burn after the ‘aliquid immensum infinitumque’ [”Something great
and immeasurable”] which Cicero desired” (Jan-Feb 1827 journal entry at age 23)(Emerson 2001, 487). At the same time, however, he was
filled with doubt: “a score of words & deeds issue from me daily, of which
I am not the master. They are begotten
of weakness & born of shame” (ibid).
Yet, in time Emerson would prove that these struggles with doubt (as
well as serious illness) were a period of latency, that would yield a great
harvest in time. That harvest would be his conception of the divinity of
self-reliance, and hence, self-trust, which would give him a new confidence in
his intuitions. Emerson’s call to the
American Scholar differed more in form and style than in principle from the Divinity
School Address. Both were a call for the
“reform of Reformation” and an adaption to an age of individualism. In the manner of many Protestant ministers
before him, Emerson sought to make religion accessible to a new generation,
despite the head winds of “Copernican nihilism”. Within this context, Self-Reliance emerged as
a sympathetic union of Understanding (science/reason) and Reason (divine and
instinctual intuition), with Reason being primary. Thus, Emerson sought to
reconcile science and religion, rushing from Unitarianism to Transcendentalism.
Emerson’s struggles with self-doubt made
him particularly sensitive to the “peculiarities of the present age” (Emerson
2001, 487). In this regard, he noted that his was “the age of the first person
singular” and it was characterized by a “reform of the Reformation” (Emerson
2001, 487-8). The foundation of his faith would be self-trust, moral intuition,
and self-reliance (the search for truth in communion with one’s soul). According to Robert Milder (Emerson and the Fortunes of Godless Religion),
Reconciling the laws of nature and
the laws of morality in a postanthropomorphic universe would be a priority
throughout Emerson's career. "Calvinism rushes to be Unitarianism as
Unitarianism rushes to be Naturalism," he would remark years later about
the slippery slope from doubts of revelation and the paternity of God to doubts
of religion itself (JMN, 15:228). Could one hold fast to a religion of immanent
moral law without the stay of a divine Father, or would "Ptolemaic
Copernicanism" prove an oxymoron in fact as it was in name? Through the
early to mid 1830s, Emerson would immerse himself in the leading sciences of his
day - astronomy, chemistry, geology, botany - hoping to "humanize"
them by demonstrating that the laws of nature were indeed ethical in character
and manifestations of an anthropocentric design if not of the old
anthropomorphic Designer.” (Milder 2014, 578-9).
Emerson was not alone in feeling
that these philosophies presented a dire threat to the spiritual sanctity man
and, ultimately, the tenability of the moral order which ungirded civilization
itself. This view seemed to be in the
New England air and the refutation of this philosophy became the chief
motivation in the early days of Emerson’s thoughts (Keane 54). Emerson and
others sought to counter what Patrick Keane designated as “Hume’s potentially
nihilistic challenge” (Keane 54). These
ideological debates were intricately tied to the ongoing attempts of American
intellectuals to formulate and embody a distinct American culture that would
include “the creation of a new
literature, the literature, in a word, of democracy… Democracy had already
taken shape in America, and the democratic ideals of equality and liberty were
already deeply implanted in the American spirit, but the inmost meaning of
democracy-its new conception of the nature of man, his place in the world, and
his relation to the divine-had hardly been thought about as yet and never
adequately expressed” (Hochfield xi).
This can be seen in his 1838 address
to the Harvard Divinity School, in which he argued that “Historical
Christianity has fallen into the error that corrupts all attempts to communicate
religion. As it appears to us, and as it has appeared for ages, it is not the
doctrine of the soul, but an exaggeration of the personal, the positive, the
ritual. It has dwelt, it dwells, with
noxious exaggeration about the person of Jesus.” (Emerson 2001, 73). Emerson’s chief complaint was that “the soul
is not preached” (Emerson 2001, 75). As
a result, he admonished, “the Church seems to totter to its fall, almost, all
life extinct” for “whenever the pulpit is usurped by a formalist, then is the
worshipper defrauded and disconsolate” (Emerson 2001, 75-6). Emerson concluded
that would-be ministers must “let the breath of new life be breathed by you
through the forms already existing. For, if once you are alive, you shall find
they shall become plastic and new. The remedy to their deformity is, first,
soul, and second, soul, and evermore, soul”
(Emerson 2001, 80). The soul had
to be freed from the burden of “Historical Christianity” and given new meaning
within the context of American democracy.
His audience was in possession of a “whole popedom of forms” which “one
pulsation of virtue can uplift and vivify” (Emerson 2001, 80).
Emerson sought to rally Harvard’s graduating class to this higher
calling, stating that “I look for the new Teacher, that shall follow so far
those shining laws, that he shall see them come full circle; shall see their
rounding complete grace; shall see the world to be the mirror of the soul;
shall see the identity of the law of gravitation with purity of heart; and
shall show that the Ought, that Duty, is one thing with Science, with Beauty,
and with Joy” (Emerson 2001, 81). In no uncertain terms, Emerson makes clear
that his concern is for the soul. For some, however, this criticism struck too
close to home and Emerson’s Divinity School address seems to have been his most
controversial work (Hochfield xix).
Nevertheless, throughout his life, Emerson seemed to have been
instinctively inclined towards theoretical and theological experimentation,
although this experimentation was generally ringed in by his conservative moral
character. In Self-Reliance, Emerson
continues his search for a more democratic religion that transcended
institutions, rank, and position and placed man in a direct relationship with
God and at the spiritual center of a moral and rational, anthropocentric
universal order (Woelfel 130).
Two years after the Divinity School
Address, Emerson published his first collection of essays. In Self-Reliance, Emerson returns to the
theme of the soul and its authentic and enlightening influence upon the mind of
the individual. Once again, Emerson held
the truth of the soul to be self-evident and derived from a primary relation to
truth, albeit mediated through the individual and his circumstances (Smith
206). In Self-Reliance, Emerson
elevated the wisdom of youth as a means of illustrating the self-evident nature
of morality, while conjoining it was the democratic principles of freedom,
equality, and self-reliance, elevating the insouciance of youth which refused
to be tamed. Emerson wrote that:
The nonchalance of boys who are sure
of a dinner, and would disdain as much as a lord to do or say aught to
conciliate one, is the healthy attitude of human nature. A boy is in the
parlour what the pit is in the playhouse; independent, irresponsible, looking
out from his corner on such people and facts as pass by, he tries and sentences
them on their merits, in the swift, summary way of boys, as good, bad,
interesting, silly, eloquent, troublesome. He cumbers himself never about
consequences, about interests: he gives an independent, genuine verdict. You must
court him: he does not court you. But the man is, as it were, clapped into jail
by his consciousness.
For Emerson, the concept of
“self-reliance” was spiritual; it connoted authentic, independent
thought illuminated by the light of an individual’s soul and filtered through
their unique character and temperament.
Thus, Emerson conceived of his writing as a constitutive act and a form
of experimentation directed towards this end and consciously avoided the
tendency of many philosophers to construct absolutist systemizations. Emerson himself was a perpetual
renaissance. In his
essay, The Genteel Tradition in American Philosophy: And Character and
Opinion in the United States,
George Santayana
wrote that:
Emerson
was a shrewd Yankee, by instinct on the winning side; he was a cheery,
child-like soul, impervious to the evidence of evil, as of everything that it
did not suit his transcendental individuality to appreciate or to notice…He
had no system. He opened his eyes on the world every morning with a fresh
sincerity, marking how things seemed to him then, or what they suggested to his
spontaneous fancy. This fancy, for being spontaneous, was not always novel; it
was guided by the habits and training of his mind, which were those of a
preacher. Yet he never insisted on his notions so as to turn them into settled
dogmas; he felt in his bones that they were myths…Had he made a system out of
his notion of compensation, or the over-soul, or spiritual laws, the result
would have been as thin and forced as it is in other transcendental systems.
But he coveted truth; and he returned to experience, to history, to poetry, to
the natural science of his day, for new starting-points and hints toward fresh
transcendental musings (Santayana 10).
Accordingly, his method of writing
often explores polar opposites and then inverts them.
Emerson was heavily influenced by
Stoic philosophy, in which virtue becomes a matter of pursuing that which is
sympathetic to our nature and thereby elevating ourselves. Our reason, when
properly utilized, represents the only realizable freedom available to man:
that of obeying his will, uttering his heartfelt Yes or No, and planting
himself in his self-trust (Woelfel 131).
Stoics argued that others can direct nearly unbearable disincentives at
the autonomous but only the individual can submit and ignore his higher will
(the law of his ‘universal being’); failure to do so would then be a result of
a weakness to his ‘private law’ (Woelfel 130). According to James Woelfel, author of ‘The
Beautiful Necessity’: Emerson and the Stoic Tradition, Emerson maintained a
“Platonic-Stoic conviction, expressed in the opening sentence of
"History," that "there is one mind common to all individual
men"…Emerson referred to this as the "radical identity" of all
human beings. At the same time, in the Emersonian "dialectic" the
universal identity of human beings manifests itself only in concrete individual
persons, and this is the basis of Emerson's often-misunderstood individualism
and also the ground of his affirmation of equality and democracy. This
individualism is precisely the opposite of-indeed an attack on and rejection of-individualism
as usually understood: as an atomistic autonomy in which each person stands
essentially alone, self-sufficient, and separate from others” (Woelfel 130). Similarly,
in Self-Reliance, Emerson wrote:
Trust
thyself: every heart vibrates to that iron string. Accept the place the divine
providence has found for you, the society of your contemporaries, the
connection of events. Great men have always done so, and confided themselves
childlike to the genius of their age, betraying their perception that the
absolutely trustworthy was seated at their heart, working through their hands,
predominating in all their being. And we are now men, and must accept in the
highest mind the same transcendent destiny; and not minors and invalids in a
protected corner, not cowards fleeing before a revolution, but guides,
redeemers, and benefactors, obeying the Almighty effort, and advancing on Chaos
and the Dark (Emerson 2001, 121).
Emerson’s Reason is “the essence of
genius, of virtue, and of life”; its source is “Spontaneity or Instinct”, but
namely, “Intuition” (Emerson 2001, 127).
In the manner of the Stoics, Emerson
states that “we lie in the lap of immense intelligence, which makes us
receivers of its truth and organs of its activity. When we discern justice,
when we discern truth, we do nothing of ourselves, but allow a passage to its
beams. If we ask whence this comes, if we seek to pry into the soul that
causes, all philosophy is at fault. Its presence or its absence is all we can
affirm.” (Emerson 2001, 128). Emerson thereby affirms nature, and offers a
self-evident rejection of the nihilistic tendencies of Copernican empiricism,
affirming the priority of the spiritual over the material, while reconciling
religion with science. Emerson’s embrace of nature extends to his writing, which
seems to conform to it, embracing a style that is organic, contradictory at
face value, and ultimately, irreducible; “a science baffling star, without
parallax” (Emerson 2001, 126). Emerson’s
concept of self-reliance was, in the end, more reconciliatory than revolutionary. Importantly, however, it preserved the
concept of the soul, man’s direct relationship to the Divine, and served as the
foundation for a moral order that survived the challenges of “materialists”.
Works Cited
Emerson, Ralph Waldo, et al. Emerson’s
Prose and Poetry: Authoritative Texts, Contexts, Criticism. 1st ed, W.W. Norton, 2001.
Emerson, Ralph Waldo, and Joel Porte. Essays & Lectures. Literary Classics of
the U.S. :
Distributed to the trade in the U.S. and Canada by Viking Press, 1983.
Hochfield, George. Selected Writings of the American Transcendentalists. University of
Illinois Pr., 2009.
Keane, Patrick J. Emerson, Romanticism, and Intuitive Reason: The
Transatlantic “Light of All Our Day.” University of Missouri Press, 2005.
Milder, Robert. “Emerson and the Fortunes
of Godless Religion.” The New England Quarterly, vol. 87, no. 4, Dec.
2014, pp. 573–624
Santayana, George, et al. The Genteel Tradition in American
Philosophy: And Character and Opinion in the United States. Yale University
Press, 2009.
Smith, David L. “‘Who Shall Define to Me
an Individual?’ Emerson on Self, World, and God.” American Journal of Theology &
Philosophy, vol. 30, no. 2, 2009, pp. 191–211.
Woelfel, James. “‘The Beautiful
Necessity’: Emerson and the Stoic Tradition.” American Journal of Theology &
Philosophy, vol. 32, no. 2, 2011, pp. 122–38.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.